Friedrich Schelling
Friedrich Schelling (1775-1854) was a German
idealist philosopher. Standard histories of philosophy make him the midpoint in the development of German
Idealism, situating him between Fichte, his mentor prior to 1800, and Hegel, his former
university roommate. Schelling's works were generally neglected due to being in the shadow of Hegel and his lack
of ‘empirical orientation’.
Schelling was influenced by the Jena Romantics
(1798-1804) and their mandate: “All art should become
science and all
science art; poetry and philosophy should be made one.” Schelling developed a unique form of
Idealism known as Aesthetic Idealism where he espoused the idea that only art
(‘Beauty’) was able to
harmonize and sublimate the contradictions between subjectivity (‘Goodness’) and
objectivity (‘Truth’). Schelling’s
Idealism established a synthesis between his conceptions of nature and spirit. Schelling’s Aesthetic
Idealism is visually illustrated using Integral Theory’s AQAL
map:
Walter Schulz (1912-2000), one of the
co-founders of the 1954 international conference in honor of Schelling’s centennial death, published a book
claiming that Schelling had made German idealism complete with his late philosophy, particularly with his Berlin
lectures in the 1840s. Schulz presented Schelling as the person who resolved the philosophical problems which Hegel
had left incomplete.
In "Nature is the Poetry of Mind, or How
Schelling Solved Goethe's Kantian
Problems" author Robert Richards expounds on how Schelling made an impression of Goethe:
“Schelling held that the ultimate aim of transcendental
philosophy was to bring to intuitive identity the conscious and unconscious activity that constituted the
unity of the self. With Fichte, he rejected the Kantian notion of a thing-in-itself as inconsistent and
unjustifiable. He rather argued that the unconscious activity of an absolute self-created both an empirical
self and nature as the self’s reciprocal correlate. Transcendental philosophy had the task of making this
creative activity reflectively certain on the one hand, and, on the other, to unite in intuitive synthesis
both nature, the unconscious product of self, and the conscious self, which stood over against nature — the
objective realm with the subjective, necessity with freedom. The philosopher had the task, therefore, of
bringing the intellectual intuition — that activity productive of self and non-self — up from the darkness of
unconscious operation into the light of reflective awareness. But this intellectual intuition, according to
Schelling, could be most perspicuously modeled on the aesthetic act, which united the unconscious laws of
beauty and the conscious intentions of the artist. Close examination of the creation of the aesthetic object
by the artist of genius, then, might illuminate the creation of the natural world and the empirical self by
the genius of the absolute self.
Schelling’s own
theory of genius depended upon ideas drawn from Kant, Friedrich Schiller, and Friedrich Schlegel. He interpreted
Kant’s definition of genius to mean that the artist’s unconscious nature determines those principles of beauty that
express themselves in non-conceptual feelings, which, in turn, drive conscious actions. The artist applies paint to
canvas not in light of a conscious set of rules but by relying on aesthetic feeling—the palpable surface of
underlying unconscious laws — to guide the brush.”
During the environmental concerns of the 1970s
philosophers became attracted to Schelling's single-system philosophy of nature (‘eco’) and the
intellectual (‘ego’). His influence and relation to the German art scene,
particularly to Romantic literature and visual art, has been a scientific interest since late 1960s, from
romantic painter Philipp Otto Runge (1777-1810) to visual artist Gerhard Richter and experimental artist Joseph
Beuys (1921-1986).
American philosopher Key Wilber places
Schelling as one of two philosophers who "after Plato, had the broadest impact on the Western
mind".
z
|